Socialism and Capitalism
Socialism is best defined in contrast
with capitalism, as socialism has arisen both as a critical challenge to
capitalism, and as a proposal for overcoming and replacing it. In the
classical, Marxist definition (G.A. Cohen 2000a: ch.3; Fraser 2014: 57–9),
capitalism involves certain relations of production. These comprise
certain forms of control over the productive forces—the labor power that workers deploy in
production and the means of production such as natural
resources, tools, and spaces they employ to yield goods and services—and
certain social patterns of economic interaction that typically correlate with
that control. Capitalism displays the following constitutive features:
· (i)The bulk of
the means of production is privately owned and controlled.
· (ii)People
legally own their labor power. (Here capitalism
differs from slavery and feudalism, under which systems some individuals are
entitled to control, whether completely or partially, the labor
power of others).
· (iii)Markets are
the main mechanism allocating inputs and outputs of production and determining
how societies’ productive surplus is used, including whether and how it is
consumed or invested.
An additional feature that is typically
present wherever (i)–(iii) hold, is that:
· (iv)There is
a class division between capitalists and workers, involving
specific relations (e.g., whether of bargaining, conflict, or subordination)
between those classes, and shaping the labor market,
the firm, and the broader political process.
The existence of wage labor is often seen by socialists as a necessary condition
for a society to be counted as capitalist (Schweickart
2002 [2011: 23]). Typically, workers (unlike capitalists) must sell their labor power to make a living. They sell it to capitalists,
who (unlike the workers) control the means of production. Capitalists typically
subordinate workers in the production process, as capitalists have asymmetric
decision-making power over what gets produced and how it gets produced.
Capitalists also own the output of production and sell it in the market, and
they control the predominant bulk of the flow of investment within the economy.
The relation between capitalists and workers can involve cooperation, but also
relations of conflict (e.g., regarding wages and working conditions). This
more-or-less antagonistic power relationship between capitalists and workers
plays out in a number of areas, within production itself, and in the broader
political process, as in both the economic and political domains decisions are
made about who does what, and who gets what.
There are possible economic systems that
would present exceptions, in which (iv) does not hold
even if (i), (ii) and (iii) all obtain. Examples here are a society of independent
commodity producers or a property-owning democracy (in which individuals or
groups of workers own firms). There is debate, however, as to how
feasible—accessible and stable—these are in a modern economic environment
(O’Neill 2012).
Another feature that is also typically
seen as arising where (i)–(iii) hold is this:
· (v)Production
is primarily oriented to capital accumulation (i.e., economic
production is primarily oriented to profit rather than to the satisfaction of
human needs). (G.A. Cohen 2000a; Roemer 2017).
In contrast to capitalism, socialism can
be defined as a type of society in which, at a minimum, (i) is turned into
(i*):
· (i*)The bulk of
the means of production is under social, democratic control.
Changes with regard to features (ii),
(iii), and (v) are hotly debated amongst socialists. Regarding (ii), socialists
retain the view that workers should control their labor
power, but many do not affirm the kind of absolute, libertarian property rights
in labor power that would, e.g., prevent taxation or
other forms of mandatory contribution to cater for the basic needs of others
(G.A. Cohen 1995). Regarding (iii), there is a recent burgeoning literature on
“market socialism”, which we discuss below, where proposals are advanced to
create an economy that is socialist but nevertheless features extensive
markets. Finally, regarding (v), although most socialists agree that, due to
competitive pressures, capitalists are bound to seek profit maximization, some
puzzle over whether when they do this, it is “greed and fear” and not the
generation of resources to make others besides themselves better-off that is
the dominant, more basic drive and hence the degree to which
profit-maximization should be seen as a normatively troubling phenomenon. (See
Steiner 2014, in contrast with G.A. Cohen 2009, discussing the case of
capitalists amassing capital to give it away through charity.) Furthermore,
some socialists argue that the search for profits in a market socialist economy
is not inherently suspicious (Schweickart 2002
[2011]). Most socialists, however, tend to find the profit motive problematic.
An important point about this definition
of socialism is that socialism is not equivalent to, and is arguably in
conflict with, statism. (i*) involves expansion of
social power—power based on the capacity to mobilize voluntary cooperation and
collective action—as distinct from state power—power based on the control of
rule-making and rule enforcing over a territory—as well of economic power—power
based on the control of material resources (Wright 2010). If a state controls
the economy but is not in turn democratically controlled by the individuals
engaged in economic life, what we have is some form of statism,
not socialism (
2. Three Dimensions of Socialist Views
When characterizing socialist views, it
is useful to distinguish between three dimensions of a conception of a social
justice (Gilabert 2017a). We identify these three
dimensions as:
· (DI)the core
ideals and principles animating that conception of justice;
· (DII)the social
institutions and practices implementing the ideals specified at DI;
· (DIII)the
processes of transformation leading agents and their society from where they
are currently, to the social outcome specified in DII.
The characterization of capitalism and
socialism in the previous section focuses on the social institutions and
practices constituting each form of society (i.e., on DII). We step back from
this institutional dimension in section 3, below, to consider the central
normative commitments of socialism (DI) and to survey their deployment in the
socialist critique of capitalism. We then, in section 4, engage in a more detailed discussion
of accounts of the institutional shape of socialism (DII), exploring the
various proposed implementations of socialist ideals and principles outlined
under DI. We turn to accounts of the transition to socialism (DIII) in section 5.
3. Socialist Critiques of Capitalism and
their Grounds (Dimension DI)
Socialists have condemned capitalism by
alleging that it typically features exploitation, domination, alienation, and
inefficiency. Before surveying these criticisms, it is important to note that
they rely on various ideals and principles at DI. We first mention these
grounds briefly, and then elaborate on them as we discuss their engagement in
socialists’ critical arguments. We set aside the debate, conducted mostly
during the 1980s and largely centered on the
interpretation of Marx’s writings, as to whether the condemnation of capitalism
and the advocacy for socialism relies (or should rely), on moral grounds (Geras 1985; Lukes 1985; Peffer 1990). Whereas some Marxist socialists take the view
that criticism of capitalism can be conducted without making use—either
explicitly or implicitly—of arguments with a moral foundation, our focus is on
arguments that do rely on such grounds.
Socialist Principles
Socialists have deployed ideals and
principles of equality, democracy, individual freedom, self-realization, and
community or solidarity. Regarding equality, they have proposed
strong versions of the principle of equality of opportunity according to which
everyone should have “broadly equal access to the necessary material and social
means to live flourishing lives” (Wright 2010: 12; Roemer 1994a: 11–4; Nielsen
1985). Some, but by no means all, socialists construe equality of opportunity
in a luck-egalitarian way, as requiring the neutralization of inequalities of
access to advantage that result from people’s circumstances rather than their
choices (G.A. Cohen 2009: 17–9). Socialists also embrace the ideal of democracy,
requiring that people have “broadly equal access to the necessary means to
participate meaningfully in decisions” affecting their lives (Wright 2010: 12;
Arnold n.d. [OIR]: sect. 4). Many socialists say that
democratic participation should be available not only at the level of
governmental institutions, but also in various economic arenas (such as within
the firm). Third, socialists are committed to the importance of individual
freedom. This commitment includes versions of the standard ideas of
negative liberty and non-domination (requiring security from inappropriate
interference by others). But it also typically includes a more demanding,
positive form of self-determination, as the “real freedom” of being able to
develop one’s own projects and bring them to fruition (Elster
1985: 205; Gould 1988: ch. 1; Van Parijs
1995: ch. 1; Castoriadis
1979). An ideal of self-realization through autonomously
chosen activities featuring people’s development and exercise of their creative
and productive capacities in cooperation with others sometimes informs
socialists’ positive views of freedom and equality—as in the view that there
should be a requirement of access to the conditions of self-realization at work
(Elster 1986: ch. 3).
Finally, and relatedly, socialists often affirm an idea of community or solidarity,
according to which people should organize their economic life so that they
treat the freedom and well-being of others as intrinsically significant. People
should recognize positive duties to support other people, or, as Einstein
(1949) put it, a “sense of responsibility for [their] fellow men”. Or, as Cohen
put it, people should “care about, and, where necessary and possible, care for,
one another, and, too, care that they care about one another” (G.A. Cohen 2009:
34–5). Community is sometimes presented as a moral ideal which is not itself a
demand of justice but can be used to temper problematic results permitted by
some demands of justice (such as the inequalities of outcome permitted by a
luck-egalitarian principle of equality of opportunity (G.A. Cohen 2009)).
However, community is sometimes presented within socialist views as a demand of
justice itself (Gilabert 2012). Some socialists also
take solidarity as partly shaping a desirable form of “social freedom” in which
people are able not only to advance their own good but also to act with and for
others (Honneth 2015 [2017: ch.
I]).
Given the diversity of fundamental
principles to which socialists commonly appeal, it is perhaps unsurprising that
few attempts have been made to link these principles under a unified framework.
A suggested strategy has been to articulate some aspects of them as
requirements flowing from what we might call the Abilities / Needs
Principle, following Marx’s famous dictum, in The Critique of
the Gotha Program, that a communist society should be organized so as to
realize the goals of producing and distributing “From each according to [their]
abilities, to each according to [their] needs”. This principle, presented with
brevity and in the absence of much elaboration by Marx (Marx 1875 [1978b: 531])
has been interpreted in different ways. One, descriptive interpretation simply
takes it to be a prediction of how people will feel motivated to act in a
socialist society. Another, straightforwardly normative interpretation
construes the Marxian dictum as stating duties to contribute to, and claims to
benefit from, the social product—addressing the allocation of both the burdens
and benefits of social cooperation. Its fulfillment
would, in an egalitarian and solidaristic fashion,
empower people to live flourishing lives (Carens
2003, Gilabert 2015). The normative principle itself
has also been interpreted as an articulation of the broader, and more basic,
idea of human dignity. Aiming at solidaristic
empowerment, this idea could be understood as requiring that we support
people in the pursuit of a flourishing life by not blocking, and by enabling,
the development and exercise of their valuable capacities, which are at the
basis of their moral status as agents with dignity (Gilabert
2017b).
Socialist Charges against Capitalism
Exploitation
The first typical charge leveled by socialists is that capitalism features the
exploitation of wage workers by their capitalist employers. Exploitation has
been characterized in two ways. First, in the so-called “technical” Marxist
characterization, workers are exploited by capitalists when the value embodied
in the goods they can purchase with their wages is inferior to the value
embodied in the goods they produce—with the capitalists appropriating the difference.
To maximize the profit resulting from the sale of what the workers produce,
capitalists have an incentive to keep wages low. This descriptive
characterization, which focuses on the flow of surplus labor
from workers to capitalists, differs from another common, normative
characterization of exploitation, according to which exploitation involves
taking unfair, wrongful, or unjust advantage of the productive efforts of
others. An obvious question is when, if ever, incidents of exploitation in the technical
sense involve exploitation in the normative sense. When is the transfer of
surplus labor from workers to capitalists such that
it involves wrongful advantage taking of the former by the latter? Socialists
have provided at least four answers to this question. (For
critical surveys see Arnsperger and Van Parijs 2003: ch. III; Vrousalis 2018; Wolff 1999).
The first answer is offered by the unequal
exchange account, according to which A exploits B if
and only if in their exchange A gets more than B does.
This account effectively collapses the normative sense of exploitation into the
technical one. But critics have argued that this account fails to provide
sufficient conditions for exploitation in the normative sense. Not every
unequal exchange is wrongful: it would not be wrong to transfer resources from
workers to people who (perhaps through no choice or fault of their own) are
unable to work.
A second proposal is to say that A exploits B if
and only if A gets surplus labor from B in a way that is coerced or
forced. This labor entitlement account (Holmstrom 1977; Reiman 1987)
relies on the view that workers are entitled to the product of their labor, and that capitalists wrongly deprive them of it. In
a capitalist economy, workers are compelled to transfer surplus labor to capitalists on pain of severe poverty. This is a
result of the coercively enforced system of private property rights in the
means of production. Since they do not control means of production to secure
their own subsistence, workers have no reasonable alternative to selling their labor power to capitalists and to toil on the terms favored by the latter. Critics of this approach have argued
that it, like the previous account, fails to provide sufficient conditions for
wrongful exploitation because it would (counterintuitively)
have to condemn transfers from workers to destitute people unable to work.
Furthermore, it has been argued that the account fails to provide necessary
conditions for the occurrence of exploitation. Problematic transfers of surplus
labor can occur without coercion. For example, A may
have sophisticated means of production, not obtained from others through
coercion, and hire B to work on them at a perhaps unfairly low
wage, which B voluntarily accepts despite having acceptable,
although less advantageous, alternatives (Roemer 1994b: ch.
4).
The third, unfair distribution
of productive endowments account suggests that the core problem with
capitalist exploitation (and with other forms of exploitation in class-divided
social systems) is that it proceeds against a background distribution of
initial access to productive assets that is inegalitarian. A is an exploiter,
and B is exploited, if and only if A gains
from B’s labor and A would
be worse off, and B better off, in an alternative hypothetical
economic environment in which the initial distribution of assets was equal
(with everything else remaining constant) (Roemer 1994b: 110). This account
relies on a luck-egalitarian principle of equality of opportunity. (According
to luck-egalitarianism, no one should be made worse-off than others due to
circumstances beyond their control.) Critics have argued that, because of that,
it fails to provide necessary conditions for wrongful exploitation. If A finds B stuck
in a pit, it would be wrong for A to offer B rescue
only if B signs a sweatshop contract with A—even
if B happened to have fallen into the pit after voluntarily
taking the risk to go hiking in an area well known to be dotted with such perilous
obstacles (Vrousalis 2013, 2018). Other critics worry
that this account neglects the centrality of relations of power or dominance
between exploiters and exploited (Veneziani 2013).
A fourth approach directly focuses on
the fact that exploitation typically arises when there is a significant power
asymmetry between the parties involved. The more powerful instrumentalize
and take advantage of the vulnerability of the less powerful to benefit from
this asymmetry in positions (Goodin 1987). A specific
version of this view, the domination for self-enrichment account (Vrousalis 2013, 2018), says that A exploits B if A benefits
from a transaction in which A dominates B. (On
this account, domination involves a disrespectful use of A’s power
over B.) Capitalist property rights, with the resulting unequal
access to the means of production, put propertyless
workers at the mercy of capitalists, who use their superior power over them to
extract surplus labor. A worry about this approach is
that it does not explain when the more powerful party is taking too much from
the less powerful party. For example, take a situation where A and B start
with equal assets, but A chooses to work hard while B chooses
to spend more time at leisure, so that at a later time A controls
the means of production, while B has only their own labor power. We imagine that A offers B employment,
and then ask, in light of their ex ante equal position, at
what level of wage for B and profit for A would
the transaction involve wrongful exploitation? To come to a settled view on
this question, it might be necessary to combine reliance on a principle of
freedom as non-domination with appeal to additional socialist principles
addressing just distribution—such as some version of the principles of equality
and solidarity mentioned above in section 4.1.
Interference and domination
Capitalism is often defended by saying
that it maximally extends people’s freedom, understood as the absence of
interference. Socialism would allegedly depress that freedom by prohibiting or
limiting capitalist activities such as setting up a private firm, hiring wage
workers, and keeping, investing, or spending profits. Socialists generally
acknowledge that a socialist economy would severely constrain some such
freedoms. But they point out that capitalist property rights also involve
interference. They remind us that “private property by one person presupposes
non-ownership on the part of other persons” (Marx 1991: 812) and warn that
often, although
liberals and libertarians see the freedom which
is intrinsic to capitalism, they overlook the unfreedom
which necessarily accompanies capitalist freedom. (G.A. Cohen 2011: 150)
Workers could and would be coercively
interfered with if they tried to use means of production possessed by
capitalists, to walk away with the products of their labor
in capitalist firms, or to access consumption goods they do not have enough
money to buy. In fact, every economic system opens some zones of
non-interference while closing others. Hence the appropriate question is not
whether capitalism or socialism involve interference—they both do—but whether
either of them involves more net interference, or more troubling forms of
interference, than the other. And the answer to that question is far from obvious.
It could very well be that most agents in a socialist society face less
(troublesome) interference as they pursue their projects of production and
consumption than agents in a capitalist society (G.A. Cohen 2011: chs. 7–8).
Capitalist economic relations are often
defended by saying that they are the result of free choices by consenting
adults. Wage workers are not slaves or serfs—they have the legal right to
refuse to work for capitalists. But socialists reply that the relationship
between capitalists and workers actually involves domination. Workers are
inappropriately subject to the will of capitalists in the shaping of the terms
on which they work (both in the spheres of exchange and production, and within
the broader political process). Workers’ consent to their exploitation is given
in circumstances of deep vulnerability and asymmetry of power. According to
Marx, two conditions help explain workers’ apparently free choice to enter into
a nevertheless exploitative contract: (1) in capitalism (unlike in feudalism or
slave societies) workers own their labor power, but (2)
they do not own means of production. Because of their deprivation (2), workers
have no reasonable alternative to using their entitlement (1) to sell their labor power to the capitalists—who do own the means of
production (Marx 1867 [1990: 272–3]). Through labor-saving
technical innovations spurred by competition, capitalism also constantly
produces unemployment, which weakens the bargaining power of individual workers
further. Thus, Marx says that although workers voluntarily enter into
exploitative contracts, they are “compelled [to do so] by social conditions”.
The silent compulsion of economic
relations sets the seal on the domination of the capitalist over the worker….
[The worker’s] dependence on capital … springs from the conditions of
production themselves, and is guaranteed in perpetuity by them. (Marx 1867
[1990: 382, 899])
Because of the deep background
inequality of power resulting from their structural position within a capitalist
economy, workers accept a pattern of economic transaction in which they submit
to the direction of capitalists during the activities of production, and
surrender to those same capitalists a disproportional share of the fruits of
their labor. Although some individual workers might
be able to escape their vulnerable condition by saving and starting a firm of
their own, most would find this extremely difficult, and they could not all do
it simultaneously within capitalism (Elster 1985:
208–16; G.A. Cohen 1988: ch. 13).
Socialists sometimes say that capitalism
flouts an ideal of non-domination as freedom from being subject to rules one
has systematically less power to shape than others (Gourevitch
2013; Arnold 2017; Gilabert 2017b: 566–7—on which
this and the previous paragraph draw). Capitalist relations of production
involve domination and the dependence of workers on the discretion of
capitalists’ choices at three critical junctures. The first, mentioned above,
concerns the labor contract. Due to their lack of
control of the means of production, workers must largely submit, on pain of
starvation or severe poverty, to the terms capitalists offer them. The second
concerns interactions in the workplace. Capitalists and their managers rule the
activities of workers by unilaterally deciding what and how the latter produce.
Although in the sphere of circulation workers and capitalists might look
(misleadingly, given the first point) like equally free contractors striking
fair deals, once we enter the “hidden abode” of production it is clear to all
sides that what exists is relationships of intense subjection of some to the
will of others (Marx 1867 [1990: 279–80]). Workers effectively spend many of
their waking hours doing what others dictate them to do. Third, and finally,
capitalists have a disproportionate impact on the legal and political process
shaping the institutional structure of the society in which they exploit
workers, with capitalist interests dominating the political processes which in
turn set the contours of property and labor law. Even
if workers manage to obtain the legal right to vote and create their own trade
unions and parties (which labor movements achieved in
some countries after much struggle), capitalists exert disproportionate
influence via greater access to mass media, the funding of political parties,
the threat of disinvestment and capital flight if governments reduce their
profit margin, and the past and prospective recruitment of state officials in
lucrative jobs in their firms and lobbying agencies (Wright 2010: 81–4). At the
spheres of exchange, production, and in the broader political process, workers
and capitalist have asymmetric structural power. Consequently, the former are
significantly subject to the will of the latter in the shaping of the terms on
which they work (see further Wright 2000 [2015]). This inequality of structural
power, some socialists claim, is an affront to workers’ dignity as
self-determining, self-mastering agents.
The third point about domination
mentioned above is also deployed by socialists to say that capitalism conflicts
with democracy (Wright 2010: 81–4; Arnold n.d. [OIR]: sect. 4; Bowles and Gintis 1986; Meiksins Wood 1995).
Democracy requires that people have roughly equal power to affect the political
process that structures their social life—or at least that inequalities do not
reflect morally irrelevant features such as race, gender, and class. Socialists
have made three points regarding the conflict between capitalism and democracy.
The first concerns political democracy of the kind that is familiar today. Even
in the presence of multi-party electoral systems, members of the capitalist
class—despite being a minority of the population—have significantly more
influence than members of the working class. Governments have a tendency to
adapt their agendas to the wishes of capitalists because they depend on their
investment decisions to raise the taxes to fund public policies, as well as for
the variety of other reasons outlined above. Even if socialist parties win
elections, as long as they do not change the fundamentals of the economic
system, they must be congenial to the wishes of capitalists. Thus, socialists
have argued that deep changes in the economic structure of society are needed
to make electoral democracy fulfill its promise.
Political power cannot be insulated from economic power. They also, secondly,
think that such changes may be directly significant. Indeed, as radical
democrats, socialists have argued that reducing inequality of decision-making
power within the economic sphere itself is not only instrumentally significant
(to reduce inequality within the governmental sphere), but also intrinsically
significant to increase people’s self-determination in their daily lives as
economic agents. Therefore, most democratic socialists call for a solution to
the problem of the conflict between democracy and capitalism by extending
democratic principles into the economy (Fleurbaey
2006). Exploring the parallel between the political and economic systems,
socialists have argued that democratic principles should apply in the economic
arena as they do in the political domain, as economic decisions, like political
decisions, have dramatic consequences for the freedom and well-being of people.
Returning to the issue of the relations between the two arenas, socialists have
also argued that fostering workers’ self-determination in the economy (notably
in the workplace) enhances democratic participation at the political level (Coutrot 2018: ch. 9; Arnold 2012;
see survey on workplace democracy in Frega et al.
2019). A third strand of argument, finally, has explored the importance of
socialist reforms for fulfilling the ideal of a deliberative democracy in which
people participate as free and equal reasoners seeking
to make decisions that actually cater for the common good of all (J. Cohen
1989).
Alienation
As mentioned above, socialists have
included, in their affirmation of individual freedom, a specific concern
with real or effective freedom to lead
flourishing lives. This freedom is often linked with a positive ideal of self-realization,
which in turn motivates a critique of capitalism as generating alienation. This
perspective informs Marx’s views on the strong contrast between productive activity
under socialism and under capitalism. In socialism, the “realm of necessity”
and the correspondingly necessary, but typically unsavory,
labor required to secure basic subsistence would be
reduced so that people also access a “realm of freedom” in which a desirable
form of work involving creativity, cultivation of talents, and meaningful
cooperation with others is available. This realm of freedom would unleash “the
development of human energy which is an end in itself” (Marx 1991: 957–9). This
work, allowing for and facilitating individuals’ self-realization, would enable
the “all-round development of the individual”, and would in fact become a
“prime want” (Marx 1875 [1978b: 531]). The socialist society would feature “the
development of the rich individuality which is all-sided in its production as
in its consumption” (Marx 1857–8 [1973: 325]); it would constitute a “higher
form of society in which the full and free development of every individual
forms the ruling principle” (Marx 1867 [1990: 739]). By contrast, capitalism
denies the majority of the population access to self-realization at work.
Workers typically toil in tasks which are uninteresting and even stunting. They
do not control how production unfolds or what is done with the outputs of production.
And their relations with others is not one of fellowship, but rather of
domination (under their bosses) and of competition (against their fellow
workers). When alienated,
labor is external to the
worker, i.e., it does not belong to his essential being; … in his work,
therefore, he does not affirm himself but denies himself, does not feel content
but unhappy, does not develop freely his physical and mental energy but
mortifies his body and ruins his mind. … It is therefore not the satisfaction
of a need; it is merely a means to satisfy needs external to
it. (Marx 1844 [1978a: 74])
Recent scholarship has developed these
ideas further. Elster has provided the most detailed
discussion and development of the Marxian ideal of self-realization. The idea
is defined as “the full and free actualization and externalization of the
powers and the abilities of the individual” (Elster
1986: 43; 1989: 131). Self-actualization involves a two-step process in which
individuals develop their powers (e.g., learn the principles and techniques of
civil engineering) and then actualize those powers (e.g., design and
participate in the construction of a bridge). Self-externalization, in turn,
features a process in which individuals’ powers become visible to others with
the potential beneficial outcome of social recognition and the accompanying
boost in self-respect and self-esteem. However, Elster
says that this Marxian ideal must be reformulated to make it more realistic. No
one can develop all their powers fully, and no feasible economy would enable
everyone always to get exactly their first-choice jobs and conduct them only in
the ways they would most like. Furthermore, self-realization for and with
others (and thus also the combination of self-realization with community) may not
always work smoothly, as producers entangled in large and complex societies may
not feel strongly moved by the needs of distant others, and significant forms
of division of labor will likely persist. Still, Elster thinks the socialist ideal of self-realization
remains worth pursuing, for example through the generation of opportunities to
produce in worker cooperatives. Others have construed the demand for real
options to produce in ways that involve self-realization and solidarity as
significant for the implementation of the Abilities / Needs Principle (Gilabert 2015: 207–12), and defended a right to
opportunities for meaningful work against the charge that it violates a liberal
constraint of neutrality about conceptions of the good (Gilabert
2018b: sect. 3.3). (For more discussion on alienation and self-realization, see
Jaeggi 2014: ch. 10.)
Further scholarship explores recent
changes in the organization of production. Boltanski
and Chiapello argue that since the 1980s capitalism
has partly absorbed (what they dub) the “artistic critique” against de-skilled
and heteronomous work by generating schemes of economic activity in which
workers operate in teams and have significant decision-making powers. However,
these new forms of work, although common especially in certain
knowledge-intensive sectors, are not available to all workers, and they still
operate under the ultimate control of capital owners and their profit
maximizing strategies. They also operate in tandem with the elimination of the
social security policies typical of the (increasingly eroded) welfare state.
Thus, the “artistic” strand in the socialist critique of capitalism as
hampering people’s authenticity, creativity, and autonomy has not been fully
absorbed and should be renewed. It should also be combined with the other,
“social critique” strand which challenges inequality, insecurity, and
selfishness (Boltanski and Chiapello
2018: Introduction, sect. 2). Other authors find in these new forms of work the
seeds of future forms of economic organization—arguing that they provide
evidence that workers can plan and control
sophisticated processes of production on their own and that capitalists and
their managers are largely redundant (Negri 2008).
The critique of alienation has also been
recently developed further by Forst (2017) by
exploring the relation between alienation and domination. On this account, the
central problem with alienation is that it involves the denial of people’s
autonomy—their ability and right to shape their social life on terms they could
justify to themselves and to each other as free and equal co-legislators. (See
also the general analysis of the concept of alienation in Leopold 2018.)
Inefficiency
A traditional criticism of capitalism
(especially amongst Marxists) is that it is inefficient. Capitalism is prone to
cyclic crises in which wealth and human potential is destroyed and squandered.
For example, to cut costs and maximize profits, firms choose work-saving
technologies and lay off workers. But at the aggregate level, this erodes the
demand for their products, which forces firms to cut costs further (by laying off even more workers or halting production).
Socialism would, it has been argued, not be so prone to crises, as the
rationale for production would not be profit maximization but need
satisfaction. Although important, this line of criticism is less widespread
amongst contemporary socialists. Historically, capitalism has proved quite
resilient, resurrecting itself after crises and expanding its productivity dramatically
over time. In might very well be that capitalism is the best feasible regime if
the only standard of assessment were productivity.
Still, socialists point out that
capitalism involves some significant inefficiencies.
Examples are the underproduction of public goods (such as public transportation
and education), the underpricing and overconsumption
of natural resources (such as fossil fuels and fishing stocks), negative
externalities (such as pollution), the costs of monitoring and enforcing market
contracts and private property (given that the exploited may not be so keen to
work as hard as their profit-maximizing bosses require, and that the
marginalized may be moved by desperation to steal), and certain defects of
intellectual property rights (such as blocking the diffusion of innovation, and
alienating those who engage in creative activities because of their intrinsic
appeal and because of the will to serve the public rather than maximize
monetary reward) (Wright 2010: 55–65). Really existing capitalist societies
have introduced regulations to counter some of these problems, at least to some
extent. Examples are taxes and constraints to limit economic activities with
negative externalities, and public funding and subsidies to sustain activities
with positive externalities which are not sufficiently supported by the market.
But, socialists insist, such mechanisms are external to capitalism, as they
limit property rights and the scope for profit maximization as the primary
orientation in the organization of the economy. The regulations involve the
hybridization of the economic system by introducing some non-capitalist,
and even socialist elements.
There is also an important issue of
whether efficiency should only be understood in terms of maximizing production
of material consumption goods. If the metric, or the utility space, that is
taken into account when engaging in maximization assessments includes more than
these goods, then capitalism can also be criticized as inefficient on account
of its tendency to depress the availability of leisure time (as well as to
distribute it quite unequally). This carries limitation of people’s access to
the various goods that leisure enables—such as the cultivation of friendships,
family, and community or political participation. Technological innovations
create the opportunity to choose between retaining the previous level of
production while using fewer inputs (such as labor
time) or maintaining the level of inputs while
producing more. John Maynard Keynes famously held that it would be reasonable
to tend towards the prior option, and expected societies to take this path as
the technological frontier advanced (Keynes 1930/31 [2010]; Pecchi
and Piga 2010). Nevertheless, in large part because
of the profit maximization motive, capitalism displays an inherent bias in favor of the second, arguably inferior, option. Capitalism
thereby narrows the realistic options of its constituent economic agents—both
firms and individuals. Firms would lose their competitive edge and risk bankruptcy
if they did not pursue profits ahead of the broader interests of their workers
(as their products would likely be more expensive). And it is typically hard
for workers to find jobs that pay reasonable salaries for fewer hours of work.
Socialists concerned with expanding leisure time—and also with environmental
risks—find this bias quite alarming (see, e.g., G.A. Cohen 2000a: ch. XI). If a conflict between further increase in the
production of material objects for consumption and the expansion of leisure
time (and environmental protection) is unavoidable, then it is not clear, all
things considered, that the former should be prioritized, especially when an
economy has already reached a high level of material productivity.
Liberal egalitarianism and
inequality in capitalism
Capitalism has also been challenged on
liberal egalitarian grounds, and in ways that lend themselves to support for
socialism. (Rawls 2001; Barry 2005; Piketty
2014; O’Neill 2008a, 2012, 2017; Ronzoni 2018).
While many of John Rawls’s readers long took him to be a proponent of an
egalitarian form of a capitalist welfare state, or as one might put it “a
slightly imaginary Sweden”, in fact Rawls rejected such institutional
arrangements as inadequate to the task of realizing principles of political
liberty or equality of opportunity, or of keeping material inequalities within
sufficiently tight bounds. His own avowed view of the institutions that would
be needed to realize liberal egalitarian principles of justice was officially neutral
as between a form of “property-owning democracy”, which would combine private
property in the means of production with its egalitarian distribution, and
hence the abolition of the separate classes of capitalists and workers; and a
form of liberal democratic socialism that would see public ownership of the
preponderance of the means of production, with devolved control of particular
firms (Rawls 2001: 135–40; O’Neill and Williamson 2012). While Rawls’s version
of liberal democratic socialism was insufficiently developed in his own
writings, he stands as an interesting case of a theorist whose defense of a form of democratic socialism is based on
normative foundations that are not themselves distinctively socialist, but
concerned with the core liberal democratic values of justice and equality (see
also Edmundson 2017; Ypi
2018).
In a similar vein to Rawls, another
instance of a theorist who defends at least partially socialist institutional
arrangements on liberal egalitarian grounds was the Nobel Prize winning
economist James Meade. Giving a central place to decidedly liberal values of
freedom, security and independence, Meade argued that the likely levels of
socioeconomic inequality under capitalism were such that a capitalist economy
would need to be extensively tempered by socialist elements, such as the
development of a citizens’ sovereign wealth fund, if the economic system were
to be justifiable to those living under it (Meade 1964; O’Neill 2015 [OIR], 2017; O’Neill and White 2019). Looking
back before Meade, J. S. Mill can also be seen as a theorist who traveled along what we might describe as “the liberal road
to socialism”, with Mill in his Autobiography describing his
own view as the acceptance of a “qualified socialism” (Mill 1873 [2018]), and arguing
for a range of measures to create a more egalitarian economy, including making
the case for a steady-state rather than a growth-oriented economy, arguing for
workers’ collective ownership and self-management of firms in preference to the
hierarchical structures characteristic of most firms under capitalism, and
endorsing steep taxation of inheritance and unearned income (Mill 2008; see
also Ten 1998; O’Neill 2008b, Pateman 1970). More
recently, the argument has been advanced that as capitalist economies tend
towards higher levels of inequality, and in particular with the rapid velocity
at which the incomes and wealth of the very rich in society is increasing, many
of those who had seen their normative commitments as requiring only the mild
reform of capitalist economies might need to come to see the need to endorse
more radical socialist institutional proposals (Ronzoni
2018).
4. Socialist Institutional Designs
(Dimension DII)
The foregoing discussion focused on
socialist critiques of capitalism. These critiques make the case that
capitalism fails to fulfill principles, or to realize
values, to which socialists are committed. But what would an alternative
economic system look like which would fulfill those
principles, or realize those values—or at least honor
them to a larger extent? This brings us to dimension DII of socialism. We will
consider several proposed models. We will address here critical concerns about
both the feasibility and the desirability of these models. Arguments comparing
ideal socialist designs with actual capitalist societies are unsatisfactory; we
must compare like with like (Nove 1991; Brennan 2014;
Corneo 2017). Thus, we should compare ideal forms of
socialism with ideal forms of capitalism, and actual versions of capitalism
with actual versions of socialism. Most importantly, we should entertain
comparisons between the best feasible incarnations of these systems. This
requires formulating feasible forms of socialism. Feasibility assessments can
play out in two ways: they may regard the (degree of) workability and stability
of a proposed socialist system once introduced, or they may regard its (degree
of) accessibility from current conditions when it is not yet in place. We
address the former concerns in this section, leaving the latter for section 5 when we turn to dimension DIII of
socialism and the questions of socialist transition or transformation.
Central and Participatory Planning
Would socialism do better than
capitalism regarding the ideals of equality, democracy, individual freedom,
self-realization, and solidarity? This depends on the availability of workable
versions of socialism that fulfill these ideals (or
do so at least to a greater extent than workable forms of capitalism). A first
set of proposals envision an economic system that does away with both private
property in the means of production and with markets. The first version of this
model is central planning. This can be understood within a
top-down, hierarchical model. A central authority gathers information about the
technical potential in the economy and about consumers’ needs and formulates a
set of production objectives which seek an optimal match between the former and
the latter. These objectives are articulated into a plan that is passed down to
intermediate agencies and eventually to local firms, which must produce
according to the plan handed down. If it works, this proposal would secure the
highest feasible levels of equal access to consumption goods for everyone.
However, critics have argued that the model faces serious feasibility hurdles (Corneo 2017: ch. 5: Roemer 1994a:
ch. 5). It is very hard for a central authority to
gather the relevant information from producers and consumers. Second, even if
it could gather enough information, the computation of an optimal plan would
require enormously complex calculations which may be beyond the capacity of
planners (even with access to the most sophisticated technological assistance).
Finally, there may be significant incentive deficits. For example, firms might
tend to exaggerate the resources they need to produce and mislead about how
much they can produce. Without facing strong sticks and carrots (such as the
prospects for either bankruptcy and profit offered by
a competitive market), firms might well display low levels of innovation. As a
result, a planned economy would likely lag behind surrounding capitalist
economies, and their members would tend to lose faith in it. High levels of
cooperation (and willingness to innovate) could still exist if sufficiently
many individuals in this society possessed a strong sense of duty. But critics
find this unlikely to materialize, warning that “a system that only works with
exceptional individuals only works in exceptional cases” (Corneo
2017: 127).
Actual experiments in centrally planned
economies have only partially approximated the best version of it. Thus, in
addition to the problems mentioned above (which affect even that best version),
they have displayed additional defects. For example, the system introduced in the
Soviet Union featured intense concentration of political and economic power in
the hands of an elite controlling a single party
which, in turn, controlled a non-democratic state apparatus. Despite its
successes in industrializing the country (making it capable of mobilizing in a
war effort to defeat Nazi Germany), the model failed to generate sufficient
technical innovation and intensive growth to deliver differentiated consumer
goods of the kind available within advanced capitalist economies. Furthermore,
it trampled upon civil and political liberties that many socialists would
themselves hold dear.
Responding to such widespread
disempowerment, a second model for socialist planning has recommended that
planning be done in a different, more democratic way. Thus, the participatory
planning (or participatory economy, “Parecon”) model
proposes the following institutional features (Albert 2003, 2016 [OIR]). First, the means of production would
be socially owned. Second, production would take place in firms controlled by
workers (thus fostering democracy within the workplace). Third, balanced “job
complexes” are put in place in which workers can both engage in intellectual
and manual labor (thus fostering and generalizing
self-realization). Fourth, in a solidaristic fashion,
remuneration of workers would track their effort, sacrifice, and special needs
(and not their relative power or output—which would likely reflect differences
in native abilities for which they are not morally responsible). Finally, and
crucially, economic coordination would be based on comprehensive participatory
planning. This would involve a complex system of nested worker councils,
consumer councils, and an Iteration Facilitation Board. Various rounds of
deliberation within, and between, worker and consumer councils, facilitated by
this board, would be undertaken until matches between supply and demands
schedules are found—with recourse to voting procedures only when no full
agreement exists but several promising arrangements arise. This would turn the
economy into an arena of deliberative democracy.
This proposal seems to cater for the
full palette of socialist values stated in section 4.1. Importantly, it overcomes the deficits
regarding freedom displayed by central planning. Critics have warned, however,
that Parecon faces serious feasibility obstacles. In
particular, the iterative planning constituting the fifth institutional
dimension of the Parecon proposal would require
immense information complexity (Wright 2010: 260–5). It is unlikely that
participants in the operations of this board, even with the help of
sophisticated computers, would manage it sufficiently well to generate a
production plan that satisfactorily caters to the diversity of individuals’
needs. A defense of Parecon
would retort that beyond initial stages, the process of economic
decision-making would not be too cumbersome. Furthermore, it might turn out to
involve no more paperwork and time devoted to planning and to assessment behind
computer terminals than is found in existing capitalist societies (with their
myriad individual and corporate budgeting exercises, and their various
accounting and legal epicycles). And, in any case, even if it is more
cumbersome and less efficient in terms of productivity, Parecon
might still be preferable overall as an economic system, given its superior
performance regarding the values of freedom, equality, self-realization,
solidarity, and democracy
Market Socialism
Some of the above-mentioned problems of
central planning, regarding inefficiency and concentration of power, have
motivated some socialists to explore alternative economic systems in which
markets are given a central role. Markets generate problems of their own
(especially when they involve monopolies, negative externalities, and
asymmetric information). But if regulations are introduced to counter these
“market failures”, markets can be the best feasible mechanism for generating
matches between demand and supply in large, complex societies (as higher prices
signal high demand, with supply rushing to cover it, while lower prices signal
low demand, leading supply to concentrate on other products). Market
socialism affirms the traditional socialist desideratum of preventing
a division of society between a class of capitalists who do not need to work to
make a living and a class of laborers having to work
for them, but it retains from capitalism the utilization of markets to guide
production. There has been a lively debate on this approach, with several
specific systems being proposed.
One version is the economic
democracy model (Schweickart 2002 [2011],
2015 [OIR]). It has three basic features. First,
production is undertaken in firms managed by workers. Worker self-managed
enterprises would gain temporary control of some means of production (which
would be leased out by the state). Workers determine what gets produced and how
it is produced, and determine compensation schemes. Second, there is a market for
goods and services. The profit motive persists and some inequalities within and
between firms are possible, but likely much smaller than in capitalism (as
there would be no separate capitalist class, and workers will not
democratically select income schemes that involve significant inequality within
their firms). Finally, investment flows are socially controlled through
democratically accountable public investment banks, which determine funding for
enterprises on the basis of socially relevant criteria. The revenues for these
banks come from a capital assets tax. This system would (through its second
feature) mobilize the efficiency of markets while also (through its other
features) attending to socialist ideals of self-determination,
self-realization, and equal opportunity. To address some potential
difficulties, the model has been extended to include further features, such as
a commitment of the government as an employer of last resort, the creation of
socialist savings and loans associations, the accommodation of an
entrepreneurial-capitalist sector for particularly innovative small firms, and
some forms of protectionism regarding foreign trade.
Self-management market socialism has
been defended as feasible by pointing at the experience of cooperatives (such
as the Mondragón Corporation in the Basque Country in
Spain, which has (as of 2015) over 70,000 worker-owners participating in a
network of cooperative businesses). But it has also been criticized on five
counts (Corneo 2017: ch.
6). First, it would generate unfair distributions, as workers doing the same
work in different enterprises would end up with unequal income if the
enterprises are not equally successful in the market. Second, workers would
face high levels of financial risk, as their resources would be concentrated in
their firm rather than spread more widely. Third, it could generate inefficient
responses to market prices, as self-managed enterprises reduce hiring if prices
for their products are high—so that members keep more of the profit—and hire
more if the prices are low—to cover for fixed costs of production. Given the
previous point, the system could also generate high unemployment. Having the
government require firms to hire more would lead to lower productivity.
However, the further features in the model discussed above might address this
problem by allowing for small private enterprises to be formed, and by having
in the background the government play a role as an employer of last resort (although
this might also limit overall productivity). Finally, although some of the
problems of efficiency could be handled through the banks controlling
investment, it is not clear that the enormous power of such banks could be made
sufficiently accountable to a democratic process so as to avoid the potential
problem of cooptation by elites. (See, however, Malleson 2014 on democratic control of investment.)
Another market socialist model, proposed
by Carens (1981, 2003), does not impose worker
self-management. The Carensian model mirrors
the current capitalist system in most respects while introducing two key
innovative features. First, there would be direct governmental provision
regarding certain individually differentiated needs (via a public health care
system, for example). Second, to access other consumption goods, everyone
working full time would get the same post tax income. Pre-tax salaries would
vary, signaling levels of demand in the market.
People would choose jobs not only on the basis of their self-regarding
preferences, but also out of a sense of social duty to use their capacities to
support others in society. Thus, honoring the Abilities
/ Needs Principle, they would apply for jobs (within their competencies) in
which the pre-tax income is relatively high. If it worked, this model would
recruit the efficiency of markets, but it would not involve the selfish motives
and inegalitarian outcomes typically linked to them
in capitalism.
One worry about the Carensian
model is that it might be unrealistic to expect an economic system to work well
when it relies so heavily on a sense of duty to motivate people to make
cooperative contributions. This worry could be assuaged by presenting this
model as the long-term target of a socialist transformation which would
progressively develop a social ethos supporting it (Gilabert
2011, 2017a), by noting empirical findings about the significant traction of
non-egoistic motives in economic behavior (Bowles and
Gintis 2011) and the feasibility of “moral
incentives” (Guevara 1977, Lizárraga 2011), and by
exploring strategies to mobilize simultaneously various motivational mechanisms
to sustain the proposed scheme. Two other worries are the following (Gilabert 2015). First, the model makes no explicit
provision regarding real opportunities for work in self-managed firms. To cater
more fully for ideals of self-determination and self-realization, a requirement
could be added that the government promote such opportunities for those willing
to take them. Second, the model is not sufficiently sensitive to different
individual preferences regarding leisure and consumption (requiring simply that
everyone work full time and wind up with the same consumption and leisure
bundles). More flexible schedules could be introduced so that people who want
to consume more could work longer hours and have higher salaries, while people
who want to enjoy more free time could work fewer hours and have lower
salaries. Considerations of reciprocity and equality could still be honored by equalizing the incomes of those working the same
number of hours.
Many forms of market socialism allow for
some hierarchy at the point of production. These managerial forms are usually
defended on grounds of greater efficiency. But they face the question of how to
incentivize managers to behave in ways that foster innovation and productivity.
One way to do this is to set up a stock market that would help to measure the
performance of the firms they manage and to push them to make optimal
decisions. An example of this approach (there are others—Corneo
2017: ch. 8) is coupon market socialism.
In Roemer’s (1994a) version, this economic system operates with two kinds of
money: dollars (euros, pesos, etc.) and coupons. Dollars are used to purchase
commodities for consumption and production, and coupons are used in a stock
market to purchase shares in corporations. The two kinds of money are not
convertible (with an exception to be outlined below). Each person, when
reaching adulthood, is provided with an equal set of coupons. They can use them
in a state-regulated stock market (directly or through mutual investment funds)
to purchase shares in corporations at market price. They receive the dividends
from their investments in dollars, but they cannot cash the coupons themselves.
When they die, people’s coupons and shares go back to the state for
distribution to new generations—no inherited wealth is allowed—and coupons
cannot be transferred as gifts. Thus, there is no separate class of capital
owners in this economy. But there will be income inequality resulting from
people’s different fortunes with their investments (dividends) as well as from
the income they gain in the jobs they take through the labor
market (in managerial and non-managerial positions). Coupons can however be
converted into dollars by corporations; they can cash their shares to pay for
capital investments. The exchange is regulated by a public central bank.
Further, public banks or public investment funds, operating with relative
independence from the government, would steer enterprises receiving
coupons so that they maximize profit in the competitive markets for the goods
and services they produce (so that they maximize the returns on the coupons
invested). Part of that profit is also taxed for direct welfare provisions by
the state.
This model caters for ideals of equality
of opportunity (given equal distribution of coupons) and democracy (given the
elimination of capitalist dynasties that have the ability to transform massive
economic power into political influence). It also gives people freedom to
choose how to use their resources and includes solidaristic
schemes of public provision to meet needs regarding education and health care.
Via the competitive markets in consumption goods and shares, it also promises
high levels of innovation and productivity. (In some versions of the model this
is enhanced by allowing limited forms of private ownership of firms to
facilitate the input of highly innovative entrepreneurial individuals—Corneo 2017: 192–7). The model departs from traditional
forms of socialism by not exactly instituting social property
in means of production (but rather the equal dispersal of coupons across
individuals in each generation). But defenders of this model say that
socialists should not fetishize any property scheme; they should instead see
such schemes instrumentally in terms of how well they fare in the
implementation of core normative principles (such as equality of opportunity)
(Roemer 1994a: 23–4, 124–5). Critics have worries, however, that the model does
not go far enough in honoring socialist principles.
For example, they have argued that a managerial (by contrast to a
self-management) form of market socialism is deficient in terms of
self-determination and self-realization at the workplace (Satz
1996), and that the levels of inequalities in income, and the competitive
attitudes in the market that it would generate, violate ideals of community
(G.A. Cohen 2009). In response, a defender of coupon market socialism can
emphasize that the model is meant to be applied in the short-term, and that
further institutional and cultural arrangements more fully in line with
socialist principles can be introduced later on, as they become more feasible
(Roemer 1994a: 25–7, 118). A worry, however, is that the model may entrench
institutional and cultural configurations which may diminish rather than
enhance the prospects for deeper changes in the future (Brighouse 1996; Gilabert 2011).
Less Comprehensive, Piecemeal Reforms
The models discussed above envision
comprehensive “system change” in which the class division between capitalists
and wage laborers disappears. Socialists have also
explored piecemeal reforms that stop short of that structural change. An
important historical example is the combination of a market economy and
the welfare state. In this model, although property in the means of
production remains private, and markets allocate most inputs and outputs of
production, a robust governmental framework is put in place to limit the power
of capitalists over workers and to improve the life-prospects of the latter.
Thus, social insurance addresses the risks associated with illness,
unemployment, disability, and old age. Tax-funded, state provision of many of
those goods that markets typically fail to deliver for all is introduced (such
as high-quality education, public transportation, and health care). And
collective bargaining gives unions and other instruments of workers’ power some
sway on the determination of their working conditions, as well as providing an
important foundation for the political agency of the working class (O’Neill and
White 2018).
This welfare state model was developed
with great success during the three decades after World War II, especially in
Northern Europe, but also, in weaker but significant forms, in other countries
(including some in the Global South). However, since the 1980s, this model has
been in significant retreat, or even in crisis. Wealth and income inequality
have been increasing dramatically during this time (Piketty
2014; O’Neill 2017). The financial sector has become extremely powerful and
able largely to escape governmental regulation as globalization allows capital
to flow across borders. A “race to the bottom” features states competing with
each other to attract investment by lowering tax rates and other regulations,
thus undermining states’ ability to implement welfare policies (see, e.g., Dietsch 2015, 2018). Some socialists have seen this crisis
as a reason to abandon the welfare state and pursue more comprehensive changes
of the kind discussed above. Others, however, have argued that the model should
be defended given that it has been proven to work quite well while the
alternatives have uncertain prospects.